Re: There is No Altruism

From: Eliezer S. Yudkowsky (sentience@pobox.com)
Date: Wed Mar 23 2005 - 15:05:09 MST


 From http://sl4.org/wiki/DialogueOnFriendliness
(Eliezer-2003 era, partially superceded by CollectiveVolition)

Cathryn: All right. Suppose I wished for the genie to grab an ice cream
cone from a little girl and give it to me. Now it might be a really
delicious and satisfying ice cream cone, but it would still be wrong to
take the ice cream cone away from the little girl. Isn't your definition
of satisfaction fundamentally selfish?

Dennis: I'll say! *I* should get the ice cream cone.

Bernard: Well, of course, the so-called altruist is also really selfish.
It's just that the altruist is made happy by other people's happiness,
so he tries to make other people happy in order to increase his own
happiness.

Cathryn: That sounds like a silly definition. It sounds like a bunch of
philosophers trying to get rid of the inconvenient square peg of
altruism by stuffing it into an ill-fitting round hole. That is just not
how altruism actually works in real people, Bernard.

Autrey: I wouldn't dismiss the thought entirely. The philosopher Raymond
Smullyan once asked: "Is altruism sacrificing your own happiness for the
happiness of others, or gaining your happiness through the happiness of
others?" I think that's a penetrating question.

Eileen: I would say that altruism is making choices so as to maximize
the expected happiness of others. My favorite definition of altruism is
one I found in a glossary of Zen: "Altruistic behavior: An act done
without any intent for personal gain in any form. Altruism requires that
there is no want for material, physical, spiritual, or egoistic gain."

Cathryn: No *spiritual* gain?

Eileen: That's right.

Bernard: That sounds like Zen, all right - self-contradictory,
inherently impossible of realization. Different people are made happy by
different things, but everyone does what makes them happy. If the
altruist were not made happy by the thought of helping others, he
wouldn't do it.

Autrey: I may be made happy by the thought of helping others. That
doesn't mean it's the reason I help others.

Cathryn: Yes, how would you account for someone who sacrifices her life
to save someone else's? She can't possibly anticipate being happy once
she's dead.

Autrey: Some people do.

Cathryn: I don't. And yet there are still things I would give my life
for. I think. You can't ever be sure until you face the crunch.

Eileen: There you go, Cathryn. There's your counterexample.

Cathryn: Huh?

Eileen: If your wish is to sacrifice your life so that someone else may
live, you can't say "Yes, I'm satisfied" afterward.

Autrey: If you have a genie on hand, you really should be able to think
of a better solution than that.

Eileen: Perhaps. Regardless, it demonstrates at least one hole in that
definition of volition.

Bernard: It is not a hole in the definition. It is never rational to
sacrifice your life for something, precisely because you will not be
around to experience the satisfaction you anticipate. A genie should not
fulfill irrational wishes.

Autrey: Cathryn knows very well that she cannot feel anything after she
dies, and yet there are still things she would die for, as would I. We
are not being tricked into that decision, we are making the choice in
full awareness of its consequences. To quote Tyrone Pow, "An atheist
giving his life for something is a profound gesture." Where is the
untrue thing that we must believe in order to make that decision? Where
is the inherent irrationality? We do not make that choice in
anticipation of feeling satisfied. We make it because some things are
more important to us than feeling satisfaction.

Bernard: Like what?

Cathryn: Like ten other people living to fulfill their own wishes. All
sentients have the same intrinsic value. If I die, and never get to
experience any satisfaction, that's more than made up for by ten other
people living to experience their own satisfactions.

Bernard: Okay, what you're saying is that other people's happiness is
weighted by your goal system the same as your own happiness, so that
when ten other people are happy, you experience ten times as much
satisfaction as when you yourself are happy. This can make it rational
to sacrifice for other people - for example, you donate a thousand
dollars to a charity that helps the poor, because the thousand dollars
can create ten times as much happiness in that charity as it could
create if you spent it on yourself. What can never be rational is
sacrificing your life, even to save ten other lives, because you won't
get to experience the satisfaction.

Cathryn: What? You're saying that you wouldn't sacrifice your own life
even to save the entire human species?

Bernard: (Laughs.) Well, I don't always do the rational thing.

Cathryn: Argh. You deserve to be locked in a cell for a week with Ayn Rand.

Autrey: Bernard, I'm not altruistic because I anticipate feeling
satisfaction. The reward is that other people benefit, not that I
experience the realization that they benefit. Given that, it is
perfectly rational to sacrifice my life to save ten people.

Bernard: But you won't ever know those ten people lived.

Autrey: So what? What I value is not "the fact that Autrey knows ten
people lived", what I value is "the fact that ten people lived". I care
about the territory, not the map. You know, this reminds me of a
conversation I once had with Greg Stock. He thought that drugs would
eventually become available that could simulate any feeling of
satisfaction, not just simple ecstasy - for example, drugs that
simulated the feeling of scientific discovery. He then went on to say
that he thought that once this happened, everyone would switch over to
taking the drugs, because real scientific discovery wouldn't be able to
compare.

Cathryn: Yikes. I wouldn't go near a drug like that with a ten-lightyear
pole.

Autrey: That's what I said, too - that I wanted to genuinely help
people, not just feel like I was doing so. "No," said Greg Stock, "you'd
take them anyway, because no matter how much you helped people, the
drugs would still make you feel ten times better."

Cathryn: That assumes I'd take the drugs to begin with, which I wouldn't
ever do. I don't want to be addicted. I don't want to be transformed
into the person those drugs would make me.

Autrey: The strange thing was that Greg Stock didn't seem to mind the
prospect. It sounded like he saw it as a natural development.

Cathryn: So where'd the conversation go after that?

Autrey: I wanted to talk about the difference between psychological
egoism and psychological altruism. But it was a bit too much territory
to cover in the thirty seconds of time I had available.

Dennis: Psychological egoism and psychological altruism? Eh?

Eileen: The difference between a goal system that optimizes an internal
state and a goal system that optimizes an external state.

Cathryn: There's a formal difference?

Eileen: Yes.

Bernard: No.

Cathryn: Interesting.

Autrey: In philosophy, this is known as the egoism debate. It's been
going on for a while. I don't really agree with the way the arguments
are usually phrased, but I can offer a quick summary anyway. You want one?

Dennis: Yeah.

Autrey: Okay. Psychological egoism is the position that all our ultimate
ends are self-directed. That is, we can want external things as means to
an end, but all our ultimate ends - all things that we desire in
themselves rather than for their consequences - are self-directed in the
sense that their propositional content is about our own states.

Eileen: Propositional content? Sounds rather GOFAI-ish.

Autrey: Maybe, but it's the way the standard debate is phrased. Anyway,
let's say I want it to be the case that I have a chocolate bar. This
desire is purely self-directed, since the propositional content mentions
me and no other agent. On the other hand, suppose I want it to be the
case that Jennie has a candy bar. This desire is other-directed, since
the propositional content mentions another person, Jennie, but not
myself. Psychological egoism claims that all our ultimate desires are
self-directed; psychological altruism says that at least some of our
ultimate desires are other-directed.

Bernard: If you want Jennie to have a candy bar, it means that you would
be happy if Jennie got a candy bar. Your real end is always happiness.

Autrey: That's known as psychological hedonism, which is a special case
of psychological egoism. As Sober and Wilson put it, "The hedonist says
that the only ultimate desires that people have are attaining pleasure
and avoding pain... the salient fact about hedonism is its claim that
people are motivational solipsists; the only things they care about
ultimately are states of their own consciousness. Although hedonists
must be egoists, the reverse isn't true. For example, if people desire
their own survival as an end in itself, they may be egoists, but they
are not hedonists." Another quote from the same authors: "Avoiding pain
is one of our ultimate goals. However, many people realize that being in
pain reduces their ability to concentrate, so they may sometimes take an
aspirin in part because they want to remove a source of distraction.
This shows that the things we want as ends in themselves we may also
want for instrumental reasons... When psychological egoism seeks to
explain why one person helped another, it isn't enough to show that one
of the reasons for helping was self-benefit; this is quite consistent
with there being another, purely altruistic, reason that the individual
had for helping. Symmetrically, to refute egoism, one need not cite
examples of helping in which only other-directed motives play a role. If
people sometimes help for both egoistic and altruistic ultimate reasons,
then psychological egoism is false."

Dennis: The very notion of altruism is incoherent.

Autrey: That argument is indeed the chief reason why some philosophers
espouse psychological hedonism.

Cathryn: Sounds like a lot of silly philosophizing to me. Does it really
matter whether I'm considered a "motivational solipsist" or whatever, as
long as I actually help people?

Bernard: That's just it! It doesn't make any operational difference -
all goal systems operate to maximize their internal satisfaction, no
matter what external events cause satisfaction.

Eileen: That's not true; it does make an operational difference. If
Autrey values the solipsistic psychological event of knowing he saved
ten lives, he will never sacrifice his own life to save ten other lives;
if he values those ten lives in themselves, he may. You told him that,
remember?

Bernard: Well, I guess Autrey might value the instantaneous happiness of
knowing he chose to save ten lives, more than he values all the
happiness he might achieve in the rest of his life.

Cathryn: That doesn't sound anything remotely like the way real people
think. Square peg, round hole.

Autrey: Do you have anything new to contribute to the debate, Eileen?
It's a pretty ancient issue in philosophy.

Eileen: The basic equation for a Bayesian decision system is usually
phrased something like D(a) = Sum U(x)P(x|a). This is known as the
expected utility equation, and it was derived by von Neumann and
Morgenstern in 1944 as a unique constraint on preference orderings for
all systems that obey certain consistency axioms -

Dennis: Start over.

Eileen: Okay. Imagine that D(a) stands for the "desirability" of an
action A, that U(x) stands for the "utility" of a state of the universe
X, and P(x|a) is your assigned "probability" that the state X occurs,
given that you take action A. For example, let's say that I show you two
spinner wheels, the red spinner and the green spinner. One-third of the
red spinner wheel is black, while two-thirds of the green spinner wheel
is white. Both spinners have a dial that I'm going to spin around until
it settles at random into a red or black area (for the red spinner) or a
white or green area (for the green spinner). The red spinner has a
one-third chance of turning up black, while the green spinner has a
two-thirds chance of turning up white. Let's say that I offer you one of
two choices; you can pick the red spinner and get a chocolate ice cream
cone if the spinner turns up black, or you can pick the green spinner
and get a vanilla ice cream cone if the spinner turns up white.

(And then it gets complicated...)

-- 
Eliezer S. Yudkowsky                          http://intelligence.org/
Research Fellow, Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence


This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Tue Feb 21 2006 - 04:22:55 MST